Sir Isaiah Berlin was a philosopher and historian of ideas, regarded as one of the leading liberal thinkers of the twentieth century. He excelled as an essayist, lecturer and conversationalist; and as a brilliant speaker who delivered, rapidly and spontaneously, richly allusive and coherently structured material, whether for a lecture series at Oxford University or as a broadcaster on the BBC Third Programme, usually without a script. Many of his essays and lectures were later collected in book form.
Born in Riga, now capital of Latvia, then part of the Russian Empire, he was the first person of Jewish descent to be elected to a prize fellowship at All Souls College, Oxford. From 1957 to 1967, he was Chichele Professor of Social and Political Theory at the University of Oxford. He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1963 to 1964. In 1966, he helped to found Wolfson College, Oxford, and became its first President. He was knighted in 1957, and was awarded the Order of Merit in 1971. He was President of the British Academy from 1974 to 1978. He also received the 1979 Jerusalem Prize for his writings on individual freedom. Berlin's work on liberal theory has had a lasting influence.
Berlin is best known for his essay Two Concepts of Liberty, delivered in 1958 as his inaugural lecture as Chichele Professor of Social and Political Theory at Oxford. He defined negative liberty as the absence of constraints on, or interference with, agents' possible action. Greater "negative freedom" meant fewer restrictions on possible action. Berlin associated positive liberty with the idea of self-mastery, or the capacity to determine oneself, to be in control of one's destiny. While Berlin granted that both concepts of liberty represent valid human ideals, as a matter of history the positive concept of liberty has proven particularly susceptible to political abuse.
Berlin contended that under the influence of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Immanuel Kant and G. W. F. Hegel (all committed to the positive concept of liberty), European political thinkers often equated liberty with forms of political discipline or constraint. This became politically dangerous when notions of positive liberty were, in the nineteenth century, used to defend nationalism, self-determination and the Communist idea of collective rational control over human destiny. Berlin argued that, following this line of thought, demands for freedom paradoxically become demands for forms of collective control and discipline – those deemed necessary for the "self-mastery" or self-determination of nations, classes, democratic communities, and even humanity as a whole. There is thus an elective affinity, for Berlin, between positive liberty and political totalitarianism.
Conversely, negative liberty represents a different, perhaps safer, understanding of the concept of liberty. Its proponents (such as Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill) insisted that constraint and discipline were the antithesis of liberty and so were (and are) less prone to confusing liberty and constraint in the manner of the philosophical harbingers of modern totalitarianism. It is this concept of Negative Liberty that Isaiah Berlin supported. It dominated heavily his early chapters in his third lecture.
This negative liberty is central to the claim for toleration due to incommensurability. This concept is mirrored in the work of Joseph Raz.
Berlin's espousal of negative liberty, his hatred of totalitarianism and his experience of Russia in the revolution and through his contact with the poet Anna Akhmatova made him an enemy of the Soviet Union and he was one of the leading public intellectuals in the ideological battle against Communism during the Cold War.
Liberty is a revised and expanded edition of the book that Isaiah Berlin regarded as his most important—Four Essays on Liberty, a standard text of liberalism, constantly in demand and constantly discussed since it was first published in 1969. Writing in Harper's, Irving Howe described it as "an exhilarating performance—this, one tells oneself, is what the life of the mind can be."
Berlin's editor Henry Hardy has revised the text, incorporating a fifth essay that Berlin himself had wanted to include. He has also added further pieces that bear on the same topic, so that Berlin's principal statements on liberty are at last available together in one volume. Finally, in an extended preface and in appendices drawn from Berlin's unpublished writings, he exhibits some of the biographical sources of Berlin's lifelong preoccupation with liberalism. These additions help us to grasp the nature of Berlin's "inner citadel," as he called it—the core of personal conviction from which some of his most influential writing sprung.
發表於2025-03-22
Liberty 2025 pdf epub mobi 電子書 下載
本文最初發錶在美國雜誌 Foreign Affairs 上。這本書的標題“自由”,論文自己的標題“二十世紀”,以及雜誌的標題“外國事務”,閤起來大概可以確定這本書的主題:二十世紀關於自由這種政治事務的 ideas。 文章一共八部分。 一,本文寫作模式 1 觀念史傢使用模式來構想材料 ...
評分總算讀瞭柏林的這本書,還順便讀瞭鄧曉芒和周楓的辯論。記得甘陽老師當初講兩種自由的區分時,是比較贊同柏林,站在消極自由的立場上的,而當時具體的語境則是對五四的反思。中國的現代之路,特彆是建國之後的曆史,被當做瞭“積極自由的爆發”的典型案例;而自由中國的重建則...
評分 評分二十個月前,我讀瞭柏林的兩個自由概念,寫瞭一點自己的想法;十個月之後,又讀瞭一遍,然後不得不為自己之前寫的東西道歉,然後又寫瞭一點評論。現在,我又讀瞭柏林的自由論,還得對於我十個月前第二次寫的東西道歉。其實我寫東西本意並無給彆人看的意思。我最近寫瞭一篇日記...
圖書標籤: 政治哲學 Berlin 思想史 Liberty IsaiahBerlin Liberalism 自由主義 伯林
書果然得多讀幾遍。其實很多話都是重復,就是把一句話換一種方式再說一遍,不過這樣對讀者很友好。伯林的論述中有個有意思的問題:自然科學方法論與形而上學看起來是對手,然而就這麼聯手瞭~
評分四年前讀過Two Concepts of Liberty,伯林也在不知不覺中影響著我的很多思考方式。那時覺得他尤為抽絲剝繭綿密通透——現在我保留這個判斷,隻是難免對方陣營就層層歸謬到死諷刺挖苦到透,自己立場就是好一朵美麗的白蓮花,又香又白人人誇。。。
評分讀Berlin就仿佛是一個英國老紳士在你對麵,語調冷靜剋製,但藏不住厚重的情懷。自由四論。還是要相信一些使人生之為人的原則,不管遙不遙遠。
評分伯林是個思想史的好老師,是少有的會像演講稿一樣安排內容的思想史作者,總是清晰地告訴讀者他要討論的是什麼問題。最愛的一篇是The Birth of Greek Individualism. 前麵的編輯手記一定要讀,非常贊!
評分伯林是個思想史的好老師,是少有的會像演講稿一樣安排內容的思想史作者,總是清晰地告訴讀者他要討論的是什麼問題。最愛的一篇是The Birth of Greek Individualism. 前麵的編輯手記一定要讀,非常贊!
Liberty 2025 pdf epub mobi 電子書 下載